121) Democracy and Development: difficult nexus
Economics and Democracy
James Galbraith reviews two books on the link between economics and democracy:
How to explain the link between economics and democracy–and how not to
Democracy Journal: Reviewed by James Galbraith (September 21, 2006):
Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy
By Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson,
A Free Nation Deep in Debt: The Financial Roots of Democracy
By James MacDonald
From where does democracy come? Is rule "by the people, for the people" ... as the great American civic faith would have us believe? Is it the most effective way to solve social problems–as John Dewey and the pragmatists argued? Or is it merely the worst system except for all the others, as Winston Churchill dismissively quipped?
These two important books–Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy by Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson and A Free Nation Deep in Debt by James MacDonald–take an economic view... They locate the origins of democracy not in ethics or social engineering, but as a side effect of the struggle for goods and services, wealth and market power. And yet, that is their only resemblance. They refer to few of the same facts and none of the same literature. Their uses of the term "economic" are totally dissimilar, and in that dissimilarity they reveal as much about the great divides within economics as they do about the origins and fate of democracy.
The contrast is ... one of substance. One book associates democracy with the material temptations of populism: Democracy arises because it redistributes income to the masses. The other sees the democratic advantage in evolutionary and comparative perspective: Democracies survive and thrive because they beat out rival systems, most especially on the battlefield, history's ultimate test of material capacity.
But behind the competing theses lies a deeper conflict of form. One book reflects the dominant spiritual tendencies of political science and neoclassical economics, rooted in methodological individualism ... The argument proceeds mathematically, by axiom and proof. Though the reference is broadly to democracy allied with capitalism, there is no discussion of credit, money, banking, financial markets, or other basic capitalist institutions...
The other book is a masterpiece of historical narrative, founded on an immense trove of numerical detail, drawn from the records of public finance and credit markets over millennia. Yet it is not the sort of "measurement without theory" that might be dismissed as redolent of the German Historical School. ... The contest between these works is thus as much a contest between the hypothetico-deductive and the evolutionary method, as it is between a "real" and a "monetary" view of economics, and as much between a theory of distribution and a theory focused on efficiency and growth. In short, they offer competing models for economics and political science. ...
For Acemoglu and Robinson, an MIT economist and a Harvard political scientist, respectively, the word "economic" signifies the neo-Benthamite doctrine of "rational choice"–a theory of behavior... To them, democracy is a process, not an end, and the preference for it is utilitarian and not a matter of values. ...
Acemoglu and Robinson do not argue that democracies are more efficient, yielding more income for everyone. Their argument is about distribution. ... Acemoglu and Robinson invoke the familiar mechanics of class conflict. All societies are divided into "elites" and "citizens." "Typically," Acemoglu and Robinson write, "there is political conflict between the elites and the citizens." ... Yet unlike Marx, Acemoglu and Robinson argue that the outcome of struggle is generally not revolution leading to proletarian dictatorship, but democracy. Wanting money, the citizens press for the vote. And, though revolutions obviously occur sometimes, democracy is simply a rational alternative: less costly to the elites, equally beneficial to the masses. In short, democracy arises because elites choose to concede it, rather than face the prospect of being disposed of unpleasantly. A few major social parameters, especially the previously existing degree of inequality, determine these relative benefits and costs. Very roughly, high degrees of inequality deepen class conflict and the resistance of elites to democracy, while very low degrees of inequality reduce the gains citizens expect from democratization. Somewhere in between there is a sweet spot, and there democracies grow. ...
Four cases illustrate their argument: Britain, Argentina, Singapore, and South Africa. In nineteenth-century Britain, Acemoglu and Robinson argue, democracy consolidated because the class differences were relatively small (try telling that to Dickens), and the elites simply decided to accept the citizens' policy preferences. In Argentina, inequality was higher and the costs of repression lower, so that democracy emerged but failed to consolidate: Cycles of democratization and repression result. In Singapore, low inequality and a low cost of repression preclude democracy: Rational citizens perceive that the struggle is not worth the trouble. In South Africa, finally, the authors argue that democratization occurred because the country became more egalitarian after the 1970s, lowering the cost to the white elites of conceding the vote to nonwhites.
This model implies and requires certain relationships in the data. ... [But] Acemoglu and Robinson's theory ... runs afoul of many cases they do not discuss. For example, India is a highly unequal yet stable democracy, for which no place exists in their model. Scandinavia, barely mentioned here, is more egalitarian than Britain (or Singapore), yet stably democratic. The collapse of communism in Eastern Europe is another problem, as the low inequality of those countries should have repressed the desire for democracy, but obviously it didn't.
Yes, sometimes the initiation of elections can be an elite concession to economic pressure from below. But ... Although they assemble facts prodigiously, one must unpleasantly conclude that when it comes to choosing the crucial ones, they have cherry-picked and also sometimes plucked "data" from thin air, in the service of selling an idea that is not so much wrong as it is far too simple. Acemoglu and Robinson's single-minded dedication to their idea is manifest in the last two-thirds of this book, which are given over to game-theoretic models, presented in mathematical form. The models are of rational social choice–the decision, by "elites" and "citizens," between dictatorship" and "democracy." They are statements of pure theory...
Work of this kind ... is not so much incomprehensible as pointless. It actually isn't incomprehensible, if you work hard enough, but the symbols are empty, and the description is not of a real society, but of an institutional vacuum, uninhabited by actual human beings, untracked by actual data. No measurement will ever test the theory. ...
And yet, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy will be heavily cited, lavishly praised, and assigned to advanced seminars in the better graduate schools. Too bad. For it isn't about democracy. It's about a cardboard caricature... In sketching their caricature, Acemoglu and Robinson strip the democratic ideal of substantial and also of ethical content. ...
Is there an alternative? If so, what would it look like? It would feature quantitative precision, married to knowledge of history, command of evidence, narrative skill, and to a fresh and important idea. Beyond this, it would give new insight into the success of democratic systems and also into the reasons they sometimes decay. As a bonus, it might help those of us predisposed to favor democracy on ethical grounds to understand that our sentiments might have a material foundation, and therefore the reasons for the loyalty we instinctively feel. It would, in other words, have many of the properties found in James MacDonald's A Free Nation Deep in Debt.
This book begins with Moses, ends with World War II, and covers just about every important development in public finance in between. Yet, for all of its historical sweep, MacDonald offers a simple, stunning thesis: Democracy arises from public debt.
For MacDonald, a British former investment banker, ... the progress of democracy is the expansion of the franchise, a word with two meanings: its present one of the right to vote and an ancient one meaning freedom from direct taxation. In turn, public debt ...[and] the institutions of finance, missing from Acemoglu and Robinson's economics, suddenly take on the pivotal role...
It's a simple but compelling argument. States exist to make war; those who win survive. Public credit is a powerful weapon; states that can borrow win wars. And so even narrow democracies, rooted in parliaments going back to the Middle Ages, have an evolutionary advantage over absolute monarchies, for the king's credit is always poor.
MacDonald pursues this story from Athens, where citizens would sacrifice their fortunes to the armies and navies when required, through the republics of Venice, Florence, and Genoa, whose citizen-creditors developed the first full-fledged public financial systems, and onward to England, France, and Spain in the age of conquest. He contrasts the strength of Anglo-Dutch finance with the repeated bankruptcies of Habsburgs and Bourbons–state finance by calculated confiscation, compounded with a privatized revenue system that deprived the crown of revenue while creating a hated class of tax farmers. It is no coincidence that Britain slowly became democratic, while revolution followed the French default of 1788.
Across the Atlantic, MacDonald traces the maturation of American public credit in the Revolutionary and Civil Wars, as well as the struggles between soft and hard money in the years following. ...
Democratic finance differs from totalitarian not because it is easy, but because it is open. Holding the liabilities of the state directly, citizen-creditors understand that they form an essential part of private financial wealth. They take a direct interest in their government and its financial affairs...
Mass democracy emerged following World War I precisely because this was the first war to be financed almost fully by the direct sale of government bonds to the public. All the Great War combatants sold bonds with zeal, and at war's end all (except bankrupt and revolutionary Russia) found themselves in debt to nearly every household in their lands. Universal suffrage had to follow; you cannot ignore your bankers, even when there are millions of them. World War II repeated and deepened the experience, and in the aftermath popular democracy reached its zenith throughout the West.
A beauty of MacDonald's idea is that it can be tested against situations he doesn't discuss. Thus the democratic decolonization of India fits: It occurred after India had become a large war-time creditor of Britain. And the struggle for democracy in Latin America is complicated by foreign debt, easily analyzed as an external electorate of enormous power–one in obvious economic conflict with the voters who, at best, only hold the internal debt...
Finally, MacDonald's financial perspective helps explain the relationship between democracy and economic development. The most democratic states are not only powerful; they are rich. They are richer than the monarchies they succeeded and also than the communist states with whom ... they competed. Why? Surely the simplest answer lies in their ability and willingness to mobilize public debt for development as well as for war. Democracies yield higher incomes not because of vulgar redistribution, which cannot distinguish them from communism, but because they alone can master the great Keynesian financial tools required for the achievement of full employment and national construction on the grand scale.
Given the simplicity and power of this argument, one reads the epilogue of this great book with surprise and sorrow. In MacDonald's view, it's all over. In the nuclear age, deficits and bond drives on the world-war scale are history, and the American citizenry has lost its pride of place as creditor of the American state. Today, financial intermediaries hold about 37 percent of U.S. public debt; Japan and China, along with other countries, now hold about 30 percent. The proportion of U.S. debt owned directly by Americans has fallen to below 10 percent; in 1945 (when the debt was more than twice as large in relation to GDP as now) citizen-creditors just about held it all. He concludes that the link is broken and "for all practical purposes, the venerable marriage between public credit and democratic government, so vital a factor in the history of the world, has been dissolved." ...
James Galbraith reviews two books on the link between economics and democracy:
How to explain the link between economics and democracy–and how not to
Democracy Journal: Reviewed by James Galbraith (September 21, 2006):
Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy
By Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson,
A Free Nation Deep in Debt: The Financial Roots of Democracy
By James MacDonald
From where does democracy come? Is rule "by the people, for the people" ... as the great American civic faith would have us believe? Is it the most effective way to solve social problems–as John Dewey and the pragmatists argued? Or is it merely the worst system except for all the others, as Winston Churchill dismissively quipped?
These two important books–Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy by Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson and A Free Nation Deep in Debt by James MacDonald–take an economic view... They locate the origins of democracy not in ethics or social engineering, but as a side effect of the struggle for goods and services, wealth and market power. And yet, that is their only resemblance. They refer to few of the same facts and none of the same literature. Their uses of the term "economic" are totally dissimilar, and in that dissimilarity they reveal as much about the great divides within economics as they do about the origins and fate of democracy.
The contrast is ... one of substance. One book associates democracy with the material temptations of populism: Democracy arises because it redistributes income to the masses. The other sees the democratic advantage in evolutionary and comparative perspective: Democracies survive and thrive because they beat out rival systems, most especially on the battlefield, history's ultimate test of material capacity.
But behind the competing theses lies a deeper conflict of form. One book reflects the dominant spiritual tendencies of political science and neoclassical economics, rooted in methodological individualism ... The argument proceeds mathematically, by axiom and proof. Though the reference is broadly to democracy allied with capitalism, there is no discussion of credit, money, banking, financial markets, or other basic capitalist institutions...
The other book is a masterpiece of historical narrative, founded on an immense trove of numerical detail, drawn from the records of public finance and credit markets over millennia. Yet it is not the sort of "measurement without theory" that might be dismissed as redolent of the German Historical School. ... The contest between these works is thus as much a contest between the hypothetico-deductive and the evolutionary method, as it is between a "real" and a "monetary" view of economics, and as much between a theory of distribution and a theory focused on efficiency and growth. In short, they offer competing models for economics and political science. ...
For Acemoglu and Robinson, an MIT economist and a Harvard political scientist, respectively, the word "economic" signifies the neo-Benthamite doctrine of "rational choice"–a theory of behavior... To them, democracy is a process, not an end, and the preference for it is utilitarian and not a matter of values. ...
Acemoglu and Robinson do not argue that democracies are more efficient, yielding more income for everyone. Their argument is about distribution. ... Acemoglu and Robinson invoke the familiar mechanics of class conflict. All societies are divided into "elites" and "citizens." "Typically," Acemoglu and Robinson write, "there is political conflict between the elites and the citizens." ... Yet unlike Marx, Acemoglu and Robinson argue that the outcome of struggle is generally not revolution leading to proletarian dictatorship, but democracy. Wanting money, the citizens press for the vote. And, though revolutions obviously occur sometimes, democracy is simply a rational alternative: less costly to the elites, equally beneficial to the masses. In short, democracy arises because elites choose to concede it, rather than face the prospect of being disposed of unpleasantly. A few major social parameters, especially the previously existing degree of inequality, determine these relative benefits and costs. Very roughly, high degrees of inequality deepen class conflict and the resistance of elites to democracy, while very low degrees of inequality reduce the gains citizens expect from democratization. Somewhere in between there is a sweet spot, and there democracies grow. ...
Four cases illustrate their argument: Britain, Argentina, Singapore, and South Africa. In nineteenth-century Britain, Acemoglu and Robinson argue, democracy consolidated because the class differences were relatively small (try telling that to Dickens), and the elites simply decided to accept the citizens' policy preferences. In Argentina, inequality was higher and the costs of repression lower, so that democracy emerged but failed to consolidate: Cycles of democratization and repression result. In Singapore, low inequality and a low cost of repression preclude democracy: Rational citizens perceive that the struggle is not worth the trouble. In South Africa, finally, the authors argue that democratization occurred because the country became more egalitarian after the 1970s, lowering the cost to the white elites of conceding the vote to nonwhites.
This model implies and requires certain relationships in the data. ... [But] Acemoglu and Robinson's theory ... runs afoul of many cases they do not discuss. For example, India is a highly unequal yet stable democracy, for which no place exists in their model. Scandinavia, barely mentioned here, is more egalitarian than Britain (or Singapore), yet stably democratic. The collapse of communism in Eastern Europe is another problem, as the low inequality of those countries should have repressed the desire for democracy, but obviously it didn't.
Yes, sometimes the initiation of elections can be an elite concession to economic pressure from below. But ... Although they assemble facts prodigiously, one must unpleasantly conclude that when it comes to choosing the crucial ones, they have cherry-picked and also sometimes plucked "data" from thin air, in the service of selling an idea that is not so much wrong as it is far too simple. Acemoglu and Robinson's single-minded dedication to their idea is manifest in the last two-thirds of this book, which are given over to game-theoretic models, presented in mathematical form. The models are of rational social choice–the decision, by "elites" and "citizens," between dictatorship" and "democracy." They are statements of pure theory...
Work of this kind ... is not so much incomprehensible as pointless. It actually isn't incomprehensible, if you work hard enough, but the symbols are empty, and the description is not of a real society, but of an institutional vacuum, uninhabited by actual human beings, untracked by actual data. No measurement will ever test the theory. ...
And yet, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy will be heavily cited, lavishly praised, and assigned to advanced seminars in the better graduate schools. Too bad. For it isn't about democracy. It's about a cardboard caricature... In sketching their caricature, Acemoglu and Robinson strip the democratic ideal of substantial and also of ethical content. ...
Is there an alternative? If so, what would it look like? It would feature quantitative precision, married to knowledge of history, command of evidence, narrative skill, and to a fresh and important idea. Beyond this, it would give new insight into the success of democratic systems and also into the reasons they sometimes decay. As a bonus, it might help those of us predisposed to favor democracy on ethical grounds to understand that our sentiments might have a material foundation, and therefore the reasons for the loyalty we instinctively feel. It would, in other words, have many of the properties found in James MacDonald's A Free Nation Deep in Debt.
This book begins with Moses, ends with World War II, and covers just about every important development in public finance in between. Yet, for all of its historical sweep, MacDonald offers a simple, stunning thesis: Democracy arises from public debt.
For MacDonald, a British former investment banker, ... the progress of democracy is the expansion of the franchise, a word with two meanings: its present one of the right to vote and an ancient one meaning freedom from direct taxation. In turn, public debt ...[and] the institutions of finance, missing from Acemoglu and Robinson's economics, suddenly take on the pivotal role...
It's a simple but compelling argument. States exist to make war; those who win survive. Public credit is a powerful weapon; states that can borrow win wars. And so even narrow democracies, rooted in parliaments going back to the Middle Ages, have an evolutionary advantage over absolute monarchies, for the king's credit is always poor.
MacDonald pursues this story from Athens, where citizens would sacrifice their fortunes to the armies and navies when required, through the republics of Venice, Florence, and Genoa, whose citizen-creditors developed the first full-fledged public financial systems, and onward to England, France, and Spain in the age of conquest. He contrasts the strength of Anglo-Dutch finance with the repeated bankruptcies of Habsburgs and Bourbons–state finance by calculated confiscation, compounded with a privatized revenue system that deprived the crown of revenue while creating a hated class of tax farmers. It is no coincidence that Britain slowly became democratic, while revolution followed the French default of 1788.
Across the Atlantic, MacDonald traces the maturation of American public credit in the Revolutionary and Civil Wars, as well as the struggles between soft and hard money in the years following. ...
Democratic finance differs from totalitarian not because it is easy, but because it is open. Holding the liabilities of the state directly, citizen-creditors understand that they form an essential part of private financial wealth. They take a direct interest in their government and its financial affairs...
Mass democracy emerged following World War I precisely because this was the first war to be financed almost fully by the direct sale of government bonds to the public. All the Great War combatants sold bonds with zeal, and at war's end all (except bankrupt and revolutionary Russia) found themselves in debt to nearly every household in their lands. Universal suffrage had to follow; you cannot ignore your bankers, even when there are millions of them. World War II repeated and deepened the experience, and in the aftermath popular democracy reached its zenith throughout the West.
A beauty of MacDonald's idea is that it can be tested against situations he doesn't discuss. Thus the democratic decolonization of India fits: It occurred after India had become a large war-time creditor of Britain. And the struggle for democracy in Latin America is complicated by foreign debt, easily analyzed as an external electorate of enormous power–one in obvious economic conflict with the voters who, at best, only hold the internal debt...
Finally, MacDonald's financial perspective helps explain the relationship between democracy and economic development. The most democratic states are not only powerful; they are rich. They are richer than the monarchies they succeeded and also than the communist states with whom ... they competed. Why? Surely the simplest answer lies in their ability and willingness to mobilize public debt for development as well as for war. Democracies yield higher incomes not because of vulgar redistribution, which cannot distinguish them from communism, but because they alone can master the great Keynesian financial tools required for the achievement of full employment and national construction on the grand scale.
Given the simplicity and power of this argument, one reads the epilogue of this great book with surprise and sorrow. In MacDonald's view, it's all over. In the nuclear age, deficits and bond drives on the world-war scale are history, and the American citizenry has lost its pride of place as creditor of the American state. Today, financial intermediaries hold about 37 percent of U.S. public debt; Japan and China, along with other countries, now hold about 30 percent. The proportion of U.S. debt owned directly by Americans has fallen to below 10 percent; in 1945 (when the debt was more than twice as large in relation to GDP as now) citizen-creditors just about held it all. He concludes that the link is broken and "for all practical purposes, the venerable marriage between public credit and democratic government, so vital a factor in the history of the world, has been dissolved." ...
0 Comments:
Postar um comentário
<< Home